Tests of Bell inequalities

نویسنده

  • Lev Vaidman
چکیده

According to recent reports, the last loopholes in testing Bell’s inequality are closed. It is argued that the really important task in this field has not been tackled yet and that the leading experiments claiming to close locality and detection efficiency loopholes, although making very significant progress, have conceptual drawbacks. The important task is constructing quantum devices which will allow winning games of certain correlated replies against any classical team. A novel game of this type is proposed.  2001 Published by Elsevier Science B.V. Quantum mechanics predicts unusual correlations between outcomes of particular experiments in spacelike separated regions. The peculiarity of these correlations is that they are stronger than any correlations explainable by a local theory. The quantum correlations, as was proven by Bell [1], break certain inequalities which have to be fulfilled if the results of every experiment are determined by some local hidden variable (LHV) theory. Recently, we have been witnessed an outstanding progress in the tests of Bell’s inequalities, but a decisive experiment which would rule out any LHV theory has not been performed yet. The deficiencies of the experiments are described by locality and detection efficiency loopholes [2]. According to recent reports, Weihs et al. [3] closed the locality loophole and Rowe et al. [4] closed the detection efficiency loophole. I want to point out that the leading experiments claiming to close the loopholes [3,4], although clearly making very significant progress, have concepE-mail address: [email protected] (L. Vaidman). tual drawbacks. These drawbacks have to be removed before claims like “the last loophole closes” can be made. Moreover, I want to argue that the experimental efforts should be turned to a slightly different task: instead of showing that the quantum correlations cannot be explained by local theories, it is more important to show that the quantum correlations can be used. Today, there is a firm consensus that there is no real question what will be the outcome of this type of experiment: the predictions of quantum theory or results conforming with the Bell inequalities. Predictions of quantum mechanics have been verified in so many experiments and with such unprecedented precision that, in spite of the very peculiar and non-intuitive features that Bell-inequality experiments demonstrate, only a minute minority of physicists believe that quantum mechanics might fail in this type of experiment. However, the fact that we are pretty sure about the final result of these experiments does not mean that we should not perform them. One goal of such experiments is to change our intuition which developed from observing 0375-9601/01/$ – see front matter  2001 Published by Elsevier Science B.V. PII: S0375-9601(01) 00 42 73 242 L. Vaidman / Physics Letters A 286 (2001) 241–244 classical phenomena. But more importantly, these experiments should lead to the stage in which we will be able to use these unusual correlations. Conceptually, the most simple, surprising, and convincing out of the Bell-type experiments is the Mermin’s version of the Greenberger–Horne–Zeilinger (GHZ) setup [5]. I find that it can be best explained as a game [6]. The team of three players is allowed to make any preparations before the players are taken to three remote locations. Then, at a certain time, each player is asked one of two possible questions: “What is X?” or “What is Y ?” to which they must quickly give one of the answers: “1” or “−1”. According to the rules of the game, either all players are asked the X question, or only one player is asked the X question and the other two are asked the Y question. The team wins if the product of their three answers is −1 in the case of three X questions and is 1 in the case of one X and two Y questions. It is a simple exercise to prove that if the answer of each player is determined by some LHV theory, then the best strategy of the team will lead to 75% probability to win. However, a quantum team equipped with ideal devices can win with certainty. Each player performs a spin measurement of a spin-1/2 particle: σx measurement for the X question and σy measurement for the Y question and gives the answer 1 for spin “up” and −1 for spin “down”. Quantum theory ensures that if the players have particles prepared in the GHZ state, the team always wins. Actually constructing such devices and seeing that, indeed, the quantum team wins the game with probability significantly larger than 75% will be a very convincing proof of Bell-type inequalities. The game need not be based on the GHZ-type “Bell inequality without inequalities” proof. A two-party game based on another proof is presented at the end of the Letter. A game-type experiment, if successful, will definitely close the detection efficiency loophole. If it is also arranged that the party asking the questions chooses them “randomly” (more about randomness below), then it will also close the locality loophole. Note, that an experiment which simultaneously closes both the detection efficiency and the locality loophole will not necessarily be suitable for winning games of the type I described here. Indeed, the current GHZ experiment [7], even if performed with ideal optical devices, cannot help to win the GHZ game. At no stage of this experiment is there a pure GHZ state. Only when the three photons were detected at three different detectors in coincidence with the fourth (trigger) photon, could we claim that the polarization state of the detected photons was the GHZ state. If a player in the team detects the trigger photon and makes a polarization measurement (the analog of the spin measurement) according to the question he is asked, he cannot be sure that the team will win since the other players would know the good answers only if they detect the photons too. However, the setup is such that there is a high probability for this not to happen even if they have 100% efficient detectors. Let me now discuss the current experiments. In order to close the locality loophole Weihs et al. [3] used fast quantum experiments to choose between local measurements. The results of these experiments are “genuinely random” according to the standard quantum theory, but are not random in the framework of LHV theories. Their outcomes are also governed by some LHVs in each site. There is enough time for information about these LHVs to reach other sites before the measurements there took place and, therefore, the locality loophole is not closed. The experiment, nevertheless, is a significant step forward because its results can be explained only by a higher level LHV theory in which hidden variables specifying the behavior of one system are influenced by hidden variables of other systems. A frequently discussed experiment in which a person at each site will have enough time to exercise his “free will” to choose between the measurements will be very convincing, but conceptually, not much better: we cannot rule out the existence of LHVs which are responsible for our seemingly “free” decisions. A better experiment for closing the locality loophole is to make the choice of the local measurements dependent on the detection of photons arriving from space-like separated events in distant galaxies. Then, the LHVtype explanation will be a “conspiracy” theory on the intergalactic scale. Now I will discuss the latest experiment by Rowe et al. [4] who claimed to close the detection efficiency loophole. In this experiment the quantum correlations were observed between results of measurements performed on two ions few micrometers apart. The detection efficiency was very high. It was admitted that the locality loophole was not closed, but the situation L. Vaidman / Physics Letters A 286 (2001) 241–244 243 was worse than that. Contrary to other experiments [3], not only the information about the choice, but also about the results of local measurements could reach other sites before completion of measurements there. The reading of the results was based on observing numerous photons emitted by the ions. This process takes time which is a few orders magnitude larger than the time it takes for the light to go from one ion to the other. Thus, one can construct a very simple LHV theory which arranges quantum correlations by “communication” between the ions during the process of measurement. It is much simpler to construct a LHV theory which employs also “outcome dependence” instead of only “parameter dependence” [8]. The purpose of closing the detection efficiency loophole was to rule out the set of LHV theories in which the particle carries, among others, instructions of the type: “if the measuring device has particular parameters, do not be detected”. Such hidden variables cannot explain the correlations of the Rowe et al. experiment and this is an important achievement. However, the task of performing an experiment closing the detection efficiency loophole without opening new loopholes (the possibility for “outcome dependence” LHV in Rowe et al.) is still open. Recently, the bizarre features of quantum mechanics have been explained through various games. Apart from the GHZ game described above there have been several other proposals: an interesting variation of the GHZ game by Steane and van Dam [9], a game based on the original Bell proof by Tsirelson [10], the “quantum cakes” game based on a non-maximally entangled state by Kwiat and Hardy [11] (see related experiment [12]). Note also the proposal of Cabello [14] for a two-party Bell-inequality proof which can be transformed into a game too. Let me present here one more game. My game is called an “impossible necklace” and it is based on the Zeno-type Bell inequalities proof [13]. A team of two players wants to persuade a third party, “the interrogator”, that they found a secret of making an “impossible necklace”. The impossible two-colored necklace has an even number of beads N and all adjacent beads are of different colors except beads 1 and N which are of the same color. The team does not want to reveal the “secret coloring”, but the players are ready to reveal the colors of any two adjacent beads of the necklace. They claim to have identical necklaces of this kind, one necklace for each player. The interrogator arranges to ask one player the color of any single bead and ask the other player, at a space-like separated region, the color of one of the adjacent beads. If the team succeeds in giving the correct answers in many repeated experiments (with new necklaces each time), a naive interrogator might be persuaded that the team knows how to make such necklaces. Indeed, if it is a “classical team”, and the players decide in advance what answer they will give for every question, then the probability to fail is at least 1/N . (There are N different pairs and there is no way to arrange that all have correct coloring.) Therefore, the probability to pass the test, say 5N times, is (1) probclassical = ( 1 − 1 N )5N ∼ e−5 ∼ 0.01. The quantum team can do much better. The players do not make any necklaces. Each player take with him a spin-1/2 particle from the EPR pair. When a player is asked the color of a bead i , he measures spin component in the direction θ̂i in the x–z plane which makes an angle θi = πi/N with the z axes. He says “green” if the result is “up”, and “red” if the result is “down”. His partner do the same. For all pairs, the measurements are in the directions which differ by the angle π/N except for the pair {1,N} in which case the angle is π(N −1)/N . Therefore, the probability to fail the test is sin2(π/2N). The probability to pass 5N tests is probquantum = ( 1− sin2 π 2N )5N ∼ ( 1 − π 2 4N2 )5N

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Two-Setting Bell Inequalities for Many Qubits

We present a family of Bell inequalities involving only two measurement settings of each party for N > 2 qubits. Our inequalities include all the standard ones with fewer than N qubits and thus gives a natural generalization. It is shown that all the Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger states violate the inequalities maximally, with an amount that grows exponentially as 2. The inequalities are also vio...

متن کامل

Bell-type inequalities for cold heteronuclear molecules.

We introduce Bell-type inequalities allowing for nonlocality and entanglement tests with two cold heteronuclear molecules. The proposed inequalities are based on correlations between each molecule spatial orientation, an observable which can be experimentally measured with present day technology. Orientation measurements are performed on each subsystem at different times. These times play the r...

متن کامل

Bipartite bell inequalities for hyperentangled states.

We show that bipartite Bell inequalities based on the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen criterion for elements of reality and derived from the properties of some hyperentangled states allow feasible experimental verification of the fact that quantum nonlocality grows exponentially with the size of the subsystems, and Bell loophole-free tests with currently available photodetection efficiencies.

متن کامل

Bell Inequalities with Postselection

Experimental tests of Bell inequalities ought to take into account all detection events. If the latter are postselected, and only some of these events are included in the statistical analysis, a Bell inequality may be violated, even by purely classical correlations. The paradoxical properties of Werner states, recently pointed out by Popescu, can be explained as the result of a postselection of...

متن کامل

Can experimental tests of Bell inequalities performed with pseudoscalar mesons be definitive ?

We discuss if experimental tests of Bell inequalities performed with pseudoscalar mesons (K or B) can be definitive. Our conclusion is that this is not the case, for the efficiency loophole cannot be eliminated. The idea that Quantum Mechanics (QM) could be an incomplete theory, representing a statistical approximation of a complete deterministic theory (where observable values are * genovese@i...

متن کامل

Logical Bell Inequalities

Bell inequalities play a central rôle in the study of quantum non-locality and entanglement, with many applications in quantum information. Despite the huge literature on Bell inequalities, it is not easy to find a clear conceptual answer to what a Bell inequality is, or a clear guiding principle as to how they may be derived. In this paper, we introduce a notion of logical Bell inequality whic...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2001